Ethics:
Moral:
Bioethics:
Properties of Ethics:
Difference between Ethics, Bioethics and Moral
Research Ethics:
Ethics in Handling of Microbes:
Ethics in Handling of Animals:
Ethics in Human Studies:
Ethical Law and Liability:
Ethics in Microbiology:
Ethics in Biotechnology:
Criticism:
comparing-beneficence-nonmaleficence
What are the Basic Principles of
Medical Ethics?
Bioethicists often refer to the four basic principles of health care ethics when evaluating the merits and difficulties of medical procedures. Ideally, for a medical practice to be considered "ethical", it must respect all four of these principles: autonomy, justice, beneficence, and non-maleficence. The use of reproductive technology raises questions in each of these areas.
Bioethics is the study of the ethical issues emerging from advances in biology and medicine. It is also moral discernment as it relates to medical policy and practice. Bioethics are concerned with the ethical questions that arise in the relationships among life sciences, biotechnology, medicine and medical ethics, politics, law, theology and philosophy.[1] It includes the study of values relating to primary care and other branches of medicine ("the ethics of the ordinary"). Ethics also relates to many other sciences outside the realm of biological sciences.
Ethics or moral philosophy is a branch of philosophy that involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong conduct. The field of ethics, along with aesthetics, concerns matters of value, and thus comprises the branch of philosophy called axiology.
Ruth Felicity Chadwick
Moral:
Bioethics:
Properties of Ethics:
Difference between Ethics, Bioethics and Moral
Research Ethics:
Ethics in Handling of Microbes:
Ethics in Handling of Animals:
Ethics in Human Studies:
Ethical Law and Liability:
Ethics in Microbiology:
Ethics in Biotechnology:
Criticism:
comparing-beneficence-nonmaleficence
- Justice is fairness. Nurses must be fair when they distribute care, for example, among the patients in the group of patients that they are taking care of. Care must be fairly, justly, and equitably distributed among a group of patients.
- Beneficence is doing good and the right thing for the patient.
- Nonmaleficence is doing no harm, as stated in the historical Hippocratic Oath. Harm can be intentional or unintentional.
- Accountability is accepting responsibility for one's own actions. Nurses are accountable for their nursing care and other actions. They must accept all of the professional and personal consequences that can occur as the result of their actions.
- Fidelity is keeping one's promises. The nurse must be faithful and true to their professional promises and responsibilities by providing high quality, safe care in a competent manner.
- Autonomy and patient self-determination are upheld when the nurse accepts the client as a unique person who has the innate right to have their own opinions, perspectives, values and beliefs. Nurses encourage patients to make their own decision without any judgments or coercion from the nurse. The patient has the right to reject or accept all treatments.
- Veracity is being completely truthful with patients; nurses must not withhold the whole truth from clients even when it may lead to patient distress.
The steps of the ethical decision making process, like the problem solving process, are:
- Problem Definition. Problem definition is the clear description of the ethical dilemma and the circumstances revolving around it.
- Data Collection. During this phase of the ethical decision making process includes a review of ethical codes, published evidence based practices, declaratory statements, professional position papers and the professional literature.
- Data Analysis. The collected data is then organized and analyzed.
- The Identification, Exploration and Generation of Possible Solutions to the Problem and the Implications of Each. All possible solutions and alternatives to resolve the ethical dilemma are explored and evaluated.
- Selecting the Best Possible Solution. All potential solutions and alternatives are considered and then the best and most ethical action is taken.
- Performing the Selected Desired Course of Action to Resolve the Ethical Dilemma
- Evaluating the Results of the Action. Like the evaluation phase of the Nursing Process, actions to resolve ethical issues are evaluated and measured in terms of their effectiveness to resolve the ethical dilemma.
As with all other aspects of nursing care, the outcomes of the interventions to promote ethical practice are evaluated and measured.
Some of the evaluation criteria that can be used to determine and evaluate the outcomes of the interventions to promote ethical practice can include one or more of the following:
- Is staff knowledgeable about ethics and ethical practice?
- Is staff effectively applying ethical principles to their daily practice?
- Are clients and staff fully knowledgeable and informed about ethics and ethical practice?
- Were all appropriate professional resources, including codes of ethics and the professional literature, employed to resolve the ethical dilemmas?
12 Ethical Principles for Business Executives
Ethical values, translated into active language establishing standards or rules describing the kind of behavior an ethical person should and should not engage in, are ethical principles. The following list
of principles incorporate the characteristics and values that most people associate with ethical behavior.
1. HONESTY. Ethical executives are honest and truthful in all their dealings and they do not deliberately mislead or deceive others by misrepresentations, overstatements, partial truths, selective omissions, or any other means.
2. INTEGRITY. Ethical executives demonstrate personal integrity and the courage of their convictions by doing what they think is right even when there is great pressure to do otherwise; they are principled, honorable and upright; they will fight for their beliefs. They will not sacrifice principle for expediency, be hypocritical, or unscrupulous.
3. PROMISE-KEEPING & TRUSTWORTHINESS. Ethical executives are worthy of trust. They are candid and forthcoming in supplying relevant information and correcting misapprehensions of fact, and they make every reasonable effort to fulfill the letter and spirit of their promises and commitments. They do not interpret agreements in an unreasonably technical or legalistic manner in order to rationalize non-compliance or create justifications for escaping their commitments.
4. LOYALTY. Ethical executives are worthy of trust, demonstrate fidelity and loyalty to persons and institutions by friendship in adversity, support and devotion to duty; they do not use or disclose information learned in confidence for personal advantage. They safeguard the ability to make independent professional judgments by scrupulously avoiding undue influences and conflicts of interest. They are loyal to their companies and colleagues and if they decide to accept other employment, they provide reasonable notice, respect the proprietary information of their former employer, and refuse to engage in any activities that take undue advantage of their previous positions.
5. FAIRNESS. Ethical executives and fair and just in all dealings; they do not exercise power arbitrarily, and do not use overreaching nor indecent means to gain or maintain any advantage nor take undue advantage of another’s mistakes or difficulties. Fair persons manifest a commitment to justice, the equal treatment of individuals, tolerance for and acceptance of diversity, the they are open-minded; they are willing to admit they are wrong and, where appropriate, change their positions and beliefs.
6. CONCERN FOR OTHERS. Ethical executives are caring, compassionate, benevolent and kind; they like the Golden Rule, help those in need, and seek to accomplish their business objectives in a manner that causes the least harm and the greatest positive good.
7. RESPECT FOR OTHERS. Ethical executives demonstrate respect for the human dignity, autonomy, privacy, rights, and interests of all those who have a stake in their decisions; they are courteous and treat all people with equal respect and dignity regardless of sex, race or national origin.
8. LAW ABIDING. Ethical executives abide by laws, rules and regulations relating to their business activities.
9. COMMITMENT TO EXCELLENCE. Ethical executives pursue excellence in performing their duties, are well informed and prepared, and constantly endeavor to increase their proficiency in all areas of responsibility.
10. LEADERSHIP. Ethical executives are conscious of the responsibilities and opportunities of their position of leadership and seek to be positive ethical role models by their own conduct and by helping to create an environment in which principled reasoning and ethical decision making are highly prized.
11. REPUTATION AND MORALE. Ethical executives seek to protect and build the company’s good reputation and the morale of its employees by engaging in no conduct that might undermine respect and by taking whatever actions are necessary to correct or prevent inappropriate conduct of others.
12. ACCOUNTABILITY. Ethical executives acknowledge and accept personal accountability for the ethical quality of their decisions and omissions to themselves, their colleagues, their companies, and their communities.
The five fundamental principles
1) Integrity
A professional accountant should be straightforward and honest in all professional and business relationships.
2) Objectivity
A professional accountant should not allow bias, conflict of interest or undue influence of others to override professional or business judgments.
3) Professional competence and due care
A professional accountant has a continuing duty to maintain professional knowledge and skill at the level required to ensure that a client or employer receives competent professional services based on current developments in practice, legislation and techniques. A professional accountant should act diligently and in accordance with applicable technical and professional standards.
4) Confidentiality
A professional accountant should respect the confidentiality of information acquired as a result of professional and business relationships and should not disclose any such information to third parties without proper and specific authority unless there is a legal or professional right or duty to disclose. Confidential information acquired as a result of professional and business relationships should not be used for the personal advantage of the professional accountant or third parties.
5) Professional behaviour
A professional accountant should comply with relevant laws and regulations and should avoid any action that discredits the profession.
Medical Ethics?
- Autonomy
- Justice
- Beneficence
- Non-maleficence
procedures. Therefore, the decision-making process must be free of coercion or coaxing. In order for a patient to
make a fully informed decision, she/he must understand all risks and benefits of the procedure and the likelihood of
success. Because ARTs are highly technical and may involve high emotions, it is difficult to expect patients to be
operating under fully-informed consent.
The idea that the burdens and benefits of new or experimental treatments must be distributed equally among all groups in
society. Requires that procedures uphold the spirit of existing laws and are fair to all players involved. The health care provider must consider four main areas when evaluating justice: fair distribution of scarce resources, competing needs, rights and obligations, and potential conflicts with established legislation. Reproductive technologies create ethical dilemmas because treatment is not equally available to all people.
Requires that the procedure be provided with the intent of doing good for the patient involved. Demands that health care providers develop and maintain skills and knowledge, continually update training, consider individual circumstances of all patients, and strive for net benefit.
Requires that a procedure does not harm the patient involved or others in society. Infertility specialists operate under the assumption that they are doing no harm or at least minimizing harm by pursuing the greater good. However, because
assistive reproductive technologies have limited success rates uncertain overall outcomes, the emotional state of the patient may be impacted negatively. In some cases, it is difficult for doctors to successfully apply the do no harm principle.
Ethics or moral philosophy is a branch of philosophy that involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong conduct. The field of ethics, along with aesthetics, concerns matters of value, and thus comprises the branch of philosophy called axiology.
What is Bioethics?
Bioethics concerns itself with addressing ethical issues in healthcare, medicine, research, biotechnology, and the environment. Typically these issues are addressed from many different disciplines. People contribute to the bioethics discussion drawing on expertise and methods from the sciences, social sciences, and the humanities. Professionals working in the field of bioethics include philosophers, scientists, health administrators, lawyers, theologians, anthropologists, disability advocates, and social workers. People may teach, do research, treat patients in the clinical setting or work to change laws or public policy. The issues of bioethics are at the intersection between medicine, law, public policy, religion, and science. Each field contributes important insights, resources and methodologies and efforts to think about or make changes to practices and policies that raise ethical concerns are often strongest when they draw on resources across disciplines. The Showcase submission formats include some commonly used formats to present bioethics-related proposals or findings.
Examples of topic areas that have been the focus of bioethics for a long time are organ donation and transplantation, genetic research, death and dying, and environmental concerns. New developments in science and technology have focused attention on topics such as assisted reproductive technologies, neuroethics (ethical issues around brain imaging and testing), and nanotechnologies (using small particles to deliver medicine or other medical treatments).
Key ethical concerns in bioethics often involve big questions such as:
- What should I do? How should I act?
- How should I treat others? What are my obligations or responsibilities toward others?
- What type of person should I be? What does it mean to be a good doctor or a good nurse or a good bench scientist?
Big moral considerations in bioethics often revolve around questions about:
- Whether one ought to act to maximize the best outcomes or ought to act to uphold important moral rules and duties? Or how to do both?
- Are we required only not to harm others or must we also act in ways that benefit them or make their lives better?
- What should be done when we think policies or law are unethical because they don’t treat people fairly or equally? What does it mean to treat people fairly?
- How could we design access to a scarce resource such that all people have a fair or maybe an equal opportunity to obtain that scarce resource, e.g., organ allocation policies?
- How and when should we share information about a medical treatment to best permit others make informed and voluntary decisions about what is done or not done to their bodies? What resources are needed to support people in making these decisions?
- When can minors make their own health care decisions? Who should decide if a minor child’s opinions about a medical treatment for them differs from that of his/her parent(s)?
Some issues about which bioethics concerns itself:
- Physician patient relationship
- Death and dying
- Resource Allocation
- Assisted reproductive techniques and their use
- Genetic testing and screening
- Sexuality and gender
- Environmental ethics
- Clinical research ethics
- Disability issues
- Consent, vulnerability, and/or coercion
- Mental health illness, treatments, and care for patients
- Ethical treatment of research subjects in clinical trials
- Ethical treatment of animals
The Connection and the Difference.
Bioethics is an area of Philosophy concerned with ethical issues arising from biomedical scientific technologies. It is a field of applied, or practical ethics. Although it is a relatively new field, it has developed swiftly over the last few decades, as new medical technologies and legal cases have thrown up ethical issues which benefit from, and are worthy of, philosophical analysis.
However, as I have already indicated, bioethics is not just a project for practical philosophers. It is by its very nature multidisciplinary, and this is one of the most important and exciting features of the field. Bioethicists learn from doctors and other scientists working in clinical and research areas of biomedicine, and the work of ethicists also sometimes also influences the legal status of activities considered in the study of bioethics in turn. The heterogeneous nature of the contributions to Bioethics enriches it as a disclipline and thereby improves its relevance and value. It is improved by being clinically, legally, and philosophically informed.
Bioethics and Medical Ethics are closely related, it is possible to describe the latter as a field within, or branch of, the former. However, the distinction between Bioethics and Medical Ethics should be clarified. Bioethics is broader, and is still mainly the domain of philosophers as I have described. However, in its development it has influenced Medical Ethics. Bioethics is generally more to do with theoretical ethical issues and concepts surrounding all biomedical technologies, such as cloning, stem cell therapy, xenotransplantation and the use of animals in research. Medical Ethics is more specific and focuses on the medical treatment of humans in particular. However, this is not to say that only doctors can do Medical Ethics. Not so, other health and social care professionals, philosophers, lawyers, and policy makers are all involved, to the benefit of the field as a whole but also particularly to doctors and patients alike.
Medical Ethics began with the Hippocratic Oath, and so has a longer history than Bioethics, which itself only really began after the Second World War, with the Nuremberg Code, and Declaration of Helsinki. Medical Ethics, as the name suggests, was historically the preserve of Doctors alone. Judges in medical law cases¹ have in the past been very deferential to doctor’s clinical judgment of good practice (although this is changing). The law associated Medical Ethics with professional guidelines and codes of practice, such as those produced by organisations like the BMA and GMC, and suggested that Medical Ethics was defined by the medical profession (in a self-regulating manner). The relationship between law and morality in this area is very rich and important and I will write more about this separately. But Medical Ethics today is not only about professional conduct.
The ‘new’ Medical Ethics is the result of the influence of Bioethics. At its core there are still issues arising from clinical practice and the development of new technologies in areas such as reproduction, end of life care and everything in between. But these issues inevitably raise deeper, more philosophical considerations such as the value of life, moral status of embryos and the significance of personhood². Hence the relevance of theoretical bioethics³ (including metabioethics as a part of metaethics, which concerns the methodology of bioethics), and the application of ethical theories such as consequentialism, deontology and virtue ethics to real, practical dilemmas as opposed to hypothetical or imaginary thought experiments. Research Ethics has always been separate, as indicated by the independent function of Clinical Ethics Committees (CEC’s) and Research Ethics Committees (REC’s), but it is obviously related to good clinical practice as practising doctors have a duty to keep up to date with new developments and treatments within their specialty, plus all treatments are developed through research. But Research Ethics is broadly concerned with ensuring that research (medical or otherwise) on human or non human animals is done in an ethical manner. Both Clinical and Research Ethics concentrate on the importance of consent, so there are areas where the two overlap. As Spike suggests, ‘each of the three fields of bioethics needs to have philosophers, doctors and lawyers in it…[and furthermore] none of these fields could exist alone‘³.
The study of Medical Ethics involves the analysis of concepts such as the doctor-patient relationship, competence, autonomy, beneficence, compassion, personhood, quality and sanctity of life, best interests and just resource allocation. Ideas like these are, I think, unique to Medical Ethics. At least, they are not considered by Bioethics or any other field in quite the same way. The work of Medical Ethics builds on that of Bioethics and enables good medical practice. It is not an activity purely for doctors, or philosophers, or others; but instead can gain from the insights of many different perspectives. Medicine allows for the practical application of the valuable contribution of these other disciplines.
THE IMPORTANCE OF BIOETHICS
02/06/2017 MIREIA RAMOS MUNTADA 3 COMENTARIS
When we talk about genetics, inevitably we can have ethics doubts. Bioethics is essential in science. Genetic modified organisms (GMO), assisted reproduction techniques (ARTs), genetic counselling, rare diseases, euthanasia and palliative care, among other topics; they have importance in bioethics. However, we have to know what bioethics is before applying it.
WHAT IS BIOETHICS?
Ethics involves the set of rules that society have agreed about living with other people for minimums, which are human rights.
Bioethics is a branch of ethics, which is the interdisciplinary study of problems created by biological and medical progress (micro and macrosocial level), and its impact in society and value system, both for now and for the future.
Bioethics concerns for ethical questions involve in human understanding of life. It born by necessity of a critic reflection about ethical conflicts, which are caused by progressing in life science and medicine. Technological and medical tools have an important role in society and it has to manage.
It is important know that bioethics does not defend a particular moral attitude nor offer determinant and definitive answers, but it searches a grounded, critic and argued reflection centred in the singularity of a concrete situation.
In bioethics we find several grounded ethical theories. Two of these are deontological ethics and utilitarian ethics.
Deontological ethics was proposed by Immanuel Kant and it consists in that reason identifies actions like good or bad, independent of their consequences.
Utilitarian ethics was proposed by Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart-Mill and it says that actions are good or bad depend on their consequences. The balance between purposes that give benefits or damage is produced by utilitarian ethics.
BASIC PRINCIPLES IN BIOETHICS
In bioethics they are four basic principles and they were proposed by Beaucham and Childress (1979):
Autonomy
Beneficence
No maleficence
Justice
These principles can be grouped in two levels:
Minimum levels: obligations that generate universal duties and these involve negative transitive duties (facts that you cannot do other people). Here, there are principles of no maleficence and justice.
Maximum levels: they are related with the choice of the vital project that every person choose to depend on their scale of values. They generate imperfect obligations: facts that I can auto impose, but I cannot call for other people (neither other people to me). Here, there are principles of autonomy and beneficence.
PRINCIPLE OF AUTONOMY
Actions are only autonomous when it exists:
Intentionality
Knowledge (it is essential)
Not external control (there are not pressures)
Authenticity (coherence with system of values and usual attitudes of the person)
An autonomous person is who has capacity to act and judge consequences of their acts and be responsible. This person has to be able to communicate his decision clear and reiterated.
PRINCIPLE OF BENEFICENCE
It has to act in benefit of person, but it can cause collateral effects.
It is important to know that you cannot do good against the other person’s will.
PRINCIPLE OF NO MALEFICENCY
You cannot harm unnecessary other people. Damage can be avoided not acting, with a passive attitude. However, good has done with active attitude.
If someone asks you, you cannot do damage.
PRINCIPLE OF JUSTICE
It involves to tract on the same way equal to equal and unequal to unequal. Vulnerable population have to receive an immediate benefit.
This principles, with principle of autonomy and beneficence (principle of no maleficence rises after), were necessary to regulate clinical trials with humans, due to Tuskegee case (Figure 1).
experimento-tuskegee
Figure 1. Researchers injecting the syphilis virus into African Americans (Source: Omicrono)
In the 60s, researchers did a clinical trial about syphilis. They wanted to see the evolution of the disease and find an alternative to painful treatments. So, they injected syphilis viruses without information of study and its consequences.
OTHER IMPORTANT PRINCIPLES
There are other important principles in bioethics.
Fidelity: protection of people, based on caution, proportionality, no discrimination and respect for people’s dignity. It includes privacy’s protection and confidentiality, keeping the promises and commitment.
Transparency: gives law and access to information. All information has to communicate clearly, comprehensively, honest and real.
Caution: based on analysis of risks. All investigations that could put at risk people’s health and future generations has to avoid.
Principle of proportionality: it is related to the principle of beneficence and looks at the relationship between the benefit obtained and the “costs” of means, human and monetary resources, risks and what the negative effects are.
Principle of non-discrimination: all persons who must be treated equally.
Principle of respect for dignity: no one has to be subjected to humiliation, must receive help in situations of need, have a minimum quality of life without suffering and freedom of action and decision, and not be used as the purpose of others.
Principle of respect for privacy and confidentiality: not unnecessarily reveal and/or interested personal and sensitive data concerning the subject. It is not an absolute principle and in front of a crime is not fulfilled.
Principle of respect for the right to information: all those involved in the process must know all the information (before, during and after the investigation).
Principle of free participation and donation: participation and donation are free and altruistic since if we are not talking about sale or exchange.
Bioethical Issues in Health Care ManagementPosted June 2, 2017 | By Tricia Hussung
Lab equiptment with title text overlay
As medical technology advances at a rapid pace, health care professionals are tasked with examining the resulting ethical dilemmas. This is where bioethics comes in. By applying the principles of ethics to the field of medicine, bioethics aims to investigate and study how health care decisions are made. It is a core component of ensuring that medical practices and procedures benefit society as a whole.
According to the Center for Practical Bioethics, those who are concerned with bioethics ask questions such as the following, within the context of modern medicine and health care:
What is the right thing to do?
What is worthwhile?
What are our obligations to one another?
Who is responsible, to whom and for what?
What is the fitting response to this moral dilemma, given the context?
On what moral grounds are such claims made?
Bioethics is a multidisciplinary field, combining philosophy, theology, history and law with medicine, nursing, health policy and the medical humanities. Because the health care system is so complex, it is important to consider relevant issues from multiple points of view.
The term “bioethics” was first introduced in 1971 to reference “the combination of biology and bioscience with humanistic knowledge,” the Center for Practical Bioethics explains. However, its application has become much broader today, including clinical decision-making, controversial new research, the implications of emerging technologies, global concerns, public policy and more. In fact, bioethics has played a central role in influencing policy changes and legislation in recent years. Its relevance for medical professionals is difficult to overstate, as the modern health care system continues to change at a rapid pace.
Bioethics has applications ranging from birth to the end of life, and it directly affects both patients and care providers. “Bioethics has an impact on every level of human community from the local nursing home to the huge international conferences on issues like the Human Genome … [It] is full of difficult ethical questions for everybody: families, hospitals, governments and civilization,” the Adelaide Centre for Bioethics and Culture explains.
The following are some of the most relevant bioethical issues faced by the health care industry.
End-of-Life Care
Elderly individuals and their families face a variety of difficult decisions as they near the end of life. Whether legal, practical, spiritual or medical in nature, the American Psychological Association notes that health care professionals overseeing these decisions “should ideally [consider them] in terms of the relief of suffering and the values and beliefs of the dying individual and his or her family.”
Advancements in medical treatment may prolong life, but quality of life can decrease once an individual becomes too ill. Then it is time to consider the level of pain management offered, whether to deliver care at home or in a hospital setting, what kind of caregiver is needed and more.
Medical Resource Allocation
When medical resources are limited or scarce, it is difficult to meet all health care needs due to a limited supply. This is why, in some cases, there is some degree of rationing in the health care system. One good example of this is intensive care units (ICUs). Patients might need to be transferred out of the ICU when they could still derive a small amount of benefit from ongoing monitoring, according to “The Ethics and Reality of Rationing in Medicine.” Decisions like this might be made to accommodate the needs of more seriously ill patients who need access to limited space in the unit.
Resource allocation could also apply to something as simple as physician time. Leaders and other stakeholders must determine which patients should be seen first and how much time should be dedicated.
Learn More About the Value of an MBA
Download our free guide, Climbing the Corporate Ladder: Your Guide to the MBA and Beyond for an in-depth look at career options, salary information, skills learned and more.
Get your copy
Eugenics
With modern advances in technology, it is possible to improve genetic quality through selective reproduction, gene selection and gene manipulation. But just because more choice exists, does that mean we should take advantage of it? That’s the ethical question behind eugenics. Options like embryo selection can allow parents to choose the sex of their child, for example. “Such possibilities raise important ethical questions – questions about which of these choices, if any, are morally wrong – along with closely related questions about the extent to which law and regulation should restrict these areas of medicine,” according to Eugenics and the Ethics of Selective Reproduction.
Euthanasia
One of the most controversial topics in bioethics is euthanasia. According to the BBC, “Euthanasia is the termination of a very sick person’s life in order to relieve them of their suffering. A person who undergoes euthanasia usually has an incurable condition.” In some cases, it may be done at the patient’s request, but when a patient is incapacitated, the decision can be made by others, such as family members or medical professionals.
In the medical community, there are two categories of euthanasia. Active euthanasia occurs when a medical professional does something that allows the patient to die. Passive euthanasia occurs when “medical professionals either don’t do something necessary to keep the patient alive, or when they stop doing something that is keeping the patient alive,” according to the BBC. It is important to note that in both cases this is done at the patient or family member’s request. The American Medical Association Code of Ethics makes a distinction between “withdrawing life-sustaining treatment” and euthanasia, which indicates just how complex this issue is.
Organ Donation
The importance of organ transplantation in modern medicine can’t be overstated. It helps patients by prolonging their lives after the failure of vital organs. For organ transplantation to work, of course, it requires donation from deceased or living individuals. According to “Ethical Issues in Organ Transplantation,” “The increasing incidence of vital organ failure and the inadequate supply of organs … has created a wide gap between organ supply and organ demand.” This means that patients often have long wait times before they receive an organ — and this can result in death. The ethical questions surrounding this issue are complex, including whether organ donation should continue to be voluntary and whether minors should be allowed to donate organs.
Bioethics and Health Care Management
For leaders in the health care field, it is important to create an ethical environment in which to deal with the daily challenges that arise. According to the National Center for Ethics in Health Care (NCEHC), ethical leadership can be achieved when managers prioritize ethics, communicate clear expectations to their employees and practice ethical decision-making.
According to the NCEHC, ethical health care organizations create a culture where individuals:
Appreciate the importance of ethics
See ethics as part of quality
Recognize and discuss ethical concerns
Understand what is expected of them
Seek consultation on ethics cases when needed
Feel empowered to behave ethically
Work to resolve ethics issues on a systems level
View organizational decisions as ethical
When managers are able to foster a culture of ethics, employee behavior is more likely to follow suit. This is one of the many important responsibilities of professionals in health care management roles.
If you are interested in health care topics like these, consider Concordia University, St. Paul’s online MBA program in Health Care Management. With coursework that focuses on both core business topics and the latest trends in the health care industry, this degree prepares graduates with the confidence to succeed in their chosen career path.
From factory working conditions at the turn of the 20th century, to today’s emphasis on diversity training, the history of workplace ethics is the ongoing story of the relationship between employees and employers.
Ethical Issues in Business
According to the Global Business Ethics Survey of 2018, employees (40%) believe that their company has a weak leaning ethical culture, and that little progress has been made to mitigate wrongdoing. Here are some of the ethical issues in business and real-world cases of how these ethical issues have affected companies.
1. Accounting
“Cooking the books” and otherwise conducting unethical accounting practices is a serious problem, especially in publicly traded companies. One of the most infamous examples is the 2001 scandal that enveloped American energy company Enron, which for years inaccurately reported its financial statements and its auditor, accounting firm Arthur Andersen, signed off on the statements despite them being incorrect. When the truth emerged, both companies went out of business, Enron’s shareholders lost $25 billion, and although the former “Big Five” accounting firm had a small portion of its employees working with Enron, the firm’s closure resulted in 85,000 jobs lost.
Although the Federal Government responded to the Enron case and other corporate scandals by creating the Sarbanes-Oxley Act in 2002, which mandates new financial reporting requirements meant to protect consumers, the “Occupy Wall Street” movement of 2011 and other issues indicate that the public still distrusts corporate financial accountability.
2. Social Media
The widespread nature of social media has made it a factor in employee conduct online and after hours. Is it ethical for companies to fire or otherwise punish employees for what they post about? Are social media posts counted as “free speech”? The line is complicated, but it is drawn when an employee’s online activities are considered disloyal to the employer, meaning that a Facebook post would go beyond complaining about work and instead do something to reduce business.
For example, a Yelp employee wrote an article on Medium, a popular blogging website, about what she perceived as awful working conditions at the influential online review company. Yelp fired her, and the author said she was let go because her post violated Yelp’s terms of conduct. Yelp’s CEO denied her claim. Was her blog post libelous, or disloyal conduct, and therefore a legitimate cause for termination? In order to avoid ambiguity, companies should create social media policies to elucidate what constitutes an infringement, especially as more states are passing off-duty conduct laws that prohibit an employer’s ability to punish an employee for online activities.
3. Harassment and Discrimination
Racial discrimination, sexual harassment, wage inequality – these are all costly ethical issues that employers and employees encounter on a daily basis across the country. According to a news release from the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC), the EEOCC secured $505 million for victims of discrimination in private sector and government workplaces in 2019. The EEOC states that there are several types of discrimination, including age, disability, equal pay, genetic information, harassment, national origin, race, religion, retaliation, pregnancy, sex and sexual harassment.
One type of discrimination, families responsibilities discrimination (FRD), has had an increase in cases of 269% over the last decade, even as other forms of employee discrimination cases have decreased. FRD is found in every industry and at every level within the company, according to a 2016 report by the Center for WorkLife Law at the UC Hastings College of Law. The report defines FRD as “when an employee suffers an adverse employment action based on unexamined biases about how workers with caregiving responsibilities will or should act, without regard to the workers’ actual performance or preferences.” FRD includes many types of family responsibilities and caregiving, including pregnancy and eldercare. For example, a father being fired for wanting to stay home to care for his sick child, or a pregnant employee not being allowed to take a break even though it was her doctor’s orders.
These cases are expected to continue to rise due to the growing number of family members who have disabilities, the increase in people 65 and older who need care, the increase of men who are becoming caregivers, and growing expectation for employees that they can work and provide family care. Employers will need to adjust to these employee perspectives and restructure how work can be accomplished to reduce FRD.
4. Health and Safety
The International Labour Organization (ILO) states that 7,397 people die every day from occupational accidents or work-related diseases. This results in more than 2.7 million deaths per year. According to the Occupational Safety & Health Administration, the top 10 most frequently cited violations of 2018 were:
Fall Protection, e.g. unprotected sides and edges and leading edges
Hazard Communication, e.g. classifying harmful chemicals
Scaffolding, e.g. required resistance and maximum weight numbers
Respiratory Protection, e.g. emergency procedures and respiratory/filter equipment standards
Lockout/Tagout, e.g. controlling hazardous energy such as oil and gas
Powered Industrial Trucks, e.g. safety requirements for fire trucks
Ladders, e.g. standards for how much weight a ladder can sustain
Electrical, Wiring Methods, i.e. procedures for how to circuit to reduce electromagnetic interference
Machine Guarding, e.g. clarifying that guillotine cutters, shears, power presses and other machines require point of operation guarding
Electrical, General Requirements; i.e. not placing conductors or equipment in damp or wet locations
Physical harm isn’t the only safety issue to be aware of, though. In 2019, an ILO report focused on rise of “psychosocial risks” and work-related stress. These risks, which include factors like job insecurity, high demands, effort-reward imbalance, and low autonomy, have been associated with health-related behavioral risks, including a sedentary lifestyle, heavy alcohol consumption, increased cigarette smoking, and eating disorders.
5. Technology/Privacy
With developments in technological security capability, employers can now monitor their employees’ activity on their computers and other company-provided electronic devices. Electronic surveillance is supposed to ensure efficiency and productivity, but when does it cross the line and become spying? Companies can legally monitor your company email and internet browser history; in fact, 66% of companies monitor internet connections, according to 2019 data from the American Management Association. 45% of employers track content, keystrokes and time spent on the keyboard, and 43% store and review computer files as well as monitor email. Overall, companies aren’t keeping this a secret: 84% told employees that they are reviewing computer activity. Employees should review the privacy policy to see how they are being monitored and consider if it can indicate a record of their job performance.
Morals are formed out of a person's values. Values are the foundation of a person's ability to judge between right and wrong. Morals build on this to form specific, context-driven rules that govern a person's behavior. They're formed from a person's life experience and are subject to opinion.
For example, someone's morals might indicate they're opposed to murder. That's a pretty general rule of thumb. But what about something more mundane? While one person's morals might tell them not to gossip, another person's morals might be quite different. They might not consider gossip to be a bad thing. Consider the following examples of morals and see how many line up with your core values and beliefs.
Morals in Society
Is there really a standard moral code in society these days? Yes, while most people follow society's laws, they also abide by certain social mores, which are governed by morals. While morals tend to be driven by personal beliefs and values, there are certainly some common morals that most people agree on, such as:
- Always tell the truth
- Do not destroy property
- Have courage
- Keep your promises
- Do not cheat
- Treat others as you want to be treated
- Do not judge
- Be dependable
- Be forgiving
- Have integrity
- Take responsibility for your actions
- Have patience
- Be loyal
- Have respect for yourself and others
- Be tolerant of differences
- Seek justice
- Have humility
- Be generous
For a deeper dive into the difference between values and morals, read What's the Difference Between Ethics, Morals, and Values?.
The Ten Commandments
The Ten Commandments are often considered the basis for societies founded on Judeo-Christian principles. You'll notice some overlap with the list above, as many of these principles are still embedded in general society.
- Do not have any gods before me
- Do not make for yourself a graven image
- Do not take the name of the Lord your God in vain
- Remember the Sabbath day to keep it holy
- Honor your father and mother
- Do not kill
- Do not commit adultery
- Do not steal
- Do not bear false witness against your neighbor
- Do not covet your neighbor's wife or possessions
Bioethics
TABLE OF CONTENTS
- Introduction
- Definition and development
- Issues in bioethics
- Approaches
- The significance of public attitudes
- Policy making
- Global bioethics
Bioethics, branch of applied ethics that studies the philosophical, social, and legal issues arising in medicine and the life sciences. It is chiefly concerned with human life and well-being, though it sometimes also treats ethical questions relating to the nonhuman biological environment. (Such questions are studied primarily in the independent fields of environmental ethics [see environmentalism] and animal rights.)
Definition and development
The range of issues considered to fall within the purview of bioethics varies depending on how broadly the field is defined. In one common usage, bioethics is more or less equivalent to medical ethics, or biomedical ethics. The term medical ethics itself has been challenged, however, in light of the growing interest in issues dealing with health care professions other than medicine, in particular nursing. The professionalization of nursing and the perception of nurses as ethically accountable in their own right have led to the development of a distinct field known as nursing ethics. Accordingly, health care ethics has come into use as a more inclusive term. Bioethics, however, is broader than this, because some of the issues it encompasses concern not so much the practice of health care as the conduct and results of research in the life sciences, especially in areas such as cloning and gene therapy (see clone and genetic engineering), stem cell research, xenotransplantation (animal-to-human transplantation), and human longevity.
Although bioethics—and indeed the whole field of applied ethics as currently understood—is a fairly recent phenomenon, there have been discussions of moral issues in medicine since ancient times. Examples include the corpus of the Greek physician Hippocrates (460–377 BC), after whom the Hippocratic oath is named (though Hippocrates himself was not its author); the Republic of Plato (428/27–348/47 BC), which advocates selective human breeding in anticipation of later programs of eugenics; the Summa contra gentiles of St. Thomas Aquinas (1224/25–1274), which briefly discusses the permissibility of abortion; and the Lectures on Ethics of the German Enlightenmentphilosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), which contains arguments against the sale of human body parts.
Bioethics emerged as a distinct field of study in the early 1960s. It was influenced not only by advances in the life sciences, particularly medicine, but also by the significant cultural and societal changes taking place at the time, primarily in the West. The perfection of certain lifesaving procedures and technologies, such as organ transplantation and kidney dialysis, required medical officials to make difficult decisions about which patients would receive treatment and which would be allowed to die. At the same time, the increasing importance placed on individual well-being contributed to changes in conventional attitudes toward marriage and sexuality, reproduction and child rearing, and civil rights. The ultimate result was widespread dissatisfaction with traditional medical paternalism and the gradual recognition of a patient’s right to be fully informed about his condition and to retain some measure of control over what happens to his body.
Issues in bioethics
The health care context
The issues studied in bioethics can be grouped into several categories. One category concerns the relationship between doctor and patient, including issues that arise from conflicts between a doctor’s duty to promote the health of his patient and the patient’s right to self-determination or autonomy, a right that in the medical context is usually taken to encompass a right to be fully informed about one’s condition and a right to be consulted about the course of one’s treatment. Is a doctor obliged to tell a patient that he is terminally ill if there is good reason to believe that doing so would hasten the patient’s death? If a patient with a life-threatening illness refuses treatment, should his wishes be respected? Should patients always be permitted to refuse the use of extraordinary life-support measures? These questions become more complicated when the patient is incapable of making rational decisions in his own interest, as in the case of infants and children, patients suffering from disabling psychiatric disorders such as schizophrenia or degenerative brain diseases such as Alzheimer disease, and patients who are in a vegetative state (seecoma).
Traditional philosophical questions
Another category of issues concerns a host of philosophical questions about the definition and significance of life and death, the nature of personhood and identity, and the extent of human freedom and individual responsibility. At what point should a fatally injured or terminally ill patient be considered dead? When his vital functions—e.g., heartbeat and breathing—have ceased? When the brain stem has ceased to function? Should the presence of deep coma be sufficient to establish death? These and similar questions were given new urgency in the 1960s, when the increased demand for human organs and tissues for use in transplant operations forced medical ethicists to establish guidelines for determining when it is permissible to remove organs from a potential donor.
At about the same time, the development of safer techniques of surgical abortion and the growing acceptability of abortion as a method of birth control prompted increasing debate about the moral status of the human fetus. In philosophical discussion, this debate was framed in terms of the notion of a “person,” understood as any being whose interests are deserving of special moral concern. The central issue was whether—and, if so, at what stage—the fetus is a person in the moral sense. In slightly different terms, the issue was whether the class of persons is coextensive with the class of human beings—whether all and only human beings are persons, or whether instead there can be human beings who are not persons or persons who are not human beings (the latter category, according to some, includes some of the higher animals and hypothetical creatures such as intelligent Martians). These questions were raised anew in later decades in response to the development of drugs, such as RU-486 (mifepristone), that induce abortion up to several weeks after conception and to the use of stem cells taken from human embryos in research on the treatment of conditions such as parkinsonism (Parkinson disease) and injuries of the central nervous system.
A closely related set of issues concerns the nature of personal identity. Recent advances in techniques of cloning, which enabled the successful cloning of animals such as sheep and rabbits, have renewed discussion of the traditional philosophical question of what, if anything, makes a particular human being the unique person he is. Is a person just the sum of the information encoded in his genes? If so, is the patient who has undergone gene therapy a different person from the one he was before—i.e., has he become someone else? If a human being were to be cloned, in what sense would he be a copy of his “parent”? Would he and his parent be the same person? If multiple human beings were cloned from the same parent, would they and their parent all be the same person?
The attempt to understand personal identity in terms of genetic information also raised anew the philosophical problems of free will and determinism. To what extent, if any, is human personality or character genetically rather than environmentally determined? Are there genetic bases for certain types of behaviour, as there seem to be for certain types of diseases (e.g., Tay-Sachs disease)? If so, what kinds of behaviour are so influenced, and to what extent are they also influenced by environmental factors? If behaviour is at least partly genetically determined, should individuals always be held fully responsible for what they do?
Finally, the possibility of developing technologies that would extend the human life span far beyond its current natural length, if not indefinitely, has led to speculation about the value of life, the significance of death, and the desirability of immortality. Is life intrinsically valuable? In cases in which one is not suffering physically or emotionally, is it always better to be alive than dead? If so, is it rational to desire immortality? What would be the significance of death in a world in which dying was not biologically inevitable?
Social and legal issues
Many of these philosophical questions, however they are answered, have significant social and legal dimensions. For example, advances in medical technology have the potential to create disproportionate disadvantages for some social groups, either by being applied in ways that harm members of the groups directly or by encouraging the adoption of social policies that discriminate unfairly against them. Accordingly, questions of discrimination in bioethics have arisen in a number of areas. In one such area, reproductive medicine, recently developed techniques have enabled parents to choose the sex of their child. Should this new power be considered liberating or oppressive? Would it be viewed positively if the vast majority of the parents who use it choose to have a boy rather than a girl? Similar concerns have been raised about the increasing use of abortion as a method of birth control in overpopulated countries such as India and China, where there is considerable social and legal pressure to limit family size and where male children are valued more highly than female children.
In the field of genetics, the use of relatively simple tests for determining a patient’s susceptibility to certain genetically transmitted diseases has led to concerns in the United States and other countries that the results of such tests, if not properly safeguarded, could be used in unfair ways by health-insurance companies, employers, and government agencies. In addition, the advent of so-called “genetic counseling”—in which prospective parents receive advice about the chances that their offspring will inherit a certain genetic disease or disorder—has allowed couples to make more-informed decisions about reproduction but also has contributed, in the view of some bioethicists, to a social atmosphere considerably less tolerant of disability than it ought to be. The same criticism has been leveled against the practice of diagnosing, and in some cases treating, congenital defects in unborn children.
Research on the genetic bases of behaviour, though still in its infancy, is controversial, and it has even been criticized as scientifically invalid. Whatever its scientific merits, however, it has the potential, according to some bioethicists, to encourage the adoption of crude models of genetic determinism in the development of social policies, especially in the areas of education and crime prevention. Such policies, it is claimed, could result in unfair discrimination against large numbers of people judged to be genetically disposed to “undesirable” forms of behaviour, such as aggression or violence.
This last point suggests a related set of issues concerning the moral status of scientific inquiry itself. The notion that there is a clear line between, on the one hand, the discovery and presentation of scientific facts and, on the other, the discussion of moral issues—the idea that moral issues arise only after scientific research is concluded—is now widely regarded as mistaken. Science is not value-neutral. Indeed, there have been ethical debates about whether certain kinds of research should be undertaken at all, irrespective of their possible applications. It has been argued, for example, that research on the possible genetic basis of homosexuality is immoral, because even the assumption that such a basis exists implicitly characterizes homosexuality as a kind of genetic abnormality. In any case, it is plausible to suggest that scientific research should always be informed by philosophy—in particular by ethics but also, arguably, by the philosophy of mind. Consideration of the moral issues related to one particular branch of medicine, namely psychiatry, makes it clear that such issues arise not only in areas of treatment but also in matters of diagnosis and classification, where the application of labels indicating illness or abnormality may create serious disadvantages for the individuals so designated.
Many of the moral issues that have arisen in the health care context and in the wake of advances in medical technology have been addressed, in whole or in part, in legislation. It is important to realize, however, that the content of such legislation is seldom, if ever, dictated by the positions one takes on particular moral issues. For example, the view that voluntary euthanasia is morally permissible in certain circumstances does not by itself settle the question of whether euthanasia should be legalized. The possibility of legalization carries with it another set of issues, such as the potential for abuse. Some bioethicists have expressed the concern that the legalization of euthanasia would create a perception among some elderly patients that society expects them to request euthanasia, even if they do not desire it, in order not to be a burden to others. Similarly, even those who believe that abortion is morally permissible in certain circumstances may consistently object to proposals to relax or eliminate laws against it.
A final class of social and legal questions concerns the allocation of health care resources. The issue of whether health care should be primarily an individual or a public responsibility remains deeply controversial. Although systems of health care allocation differ widely, they all face the problem that resources are scarce and consequently expensive. Debate has focused not only on the relative cost-effectiveness of different systems but also on the different conceptions of justice that underlie them. The global allocation of health care resources, including generic forms of drugs for life-threatening illnesses such as HIV/AIDS, is an important topic in the field of developing world bioethics.
Approaches
Traditional and contemporary ethical theories
As a branch of applied ethics, bioethics is distinct from both metaethics, the study of basic moral concepts such as ought and good, and normative ethics, the discipline that seeks to establish criteria for determining what kinds of action are morally right or wrong. To say that bioethics is “applied,” however, does not imply that it presupposes any particular ethical theory. Contemporary bioethicists make use of a variety of different views, including primarily utilitarianism and Kantianism but also more recently developed perspectives such as virtue theory and perspectives drawn from philosophical feminism, particularly the school of thought known as the ethics of care.
Utilitarianism is a normative-ethical theory that holds that the moral rightness or wrongness of an action should be ascertained in terms of the action’s consequences. According to one common formulation, an action is right if it would promote a greater amount of happiness for a greater number of people than would any other action performable in the same circumstances. The Kantian tradition, in contrast, eschews the notion of consequences and urges instead that an action is right only if it is universalizable—i.e., only if the moral rule it embodies could become a universal law applicable to all moral agents. The Kantian approach emphasizes respect for the individual, autonomy, dignity, and human rights.
Unlike these traditional approaches, both virtue ethics and the ethics of care focus on dimensions of moral theorizing other than determining the rightness or wrongness of particular actions. Virtue ethics is concerned with the nature of moral character and with the traits, capacities, or dispositions that moral agents ought to cultivate in themselves and others. Thus, the virtue ethicist may consider what character traits, such as compassion and courage, are desirable in a doctor, nurse, or biomedical researcher and how they would (or should) be manifested in various settings. The basic aim of the ethics of care is to replace—or at least augment—the supposedly “masculine” moral values of rationality, abstraction, impartiality, and independence with ostensibly more “feminine” values, such as emotion (particularly compassion and benevolence), particularity, partiality, and interdependence. From this perspective, reflection on abortion would begin not with abstract principles such as the right to autonomy or the right to life but with considerations of the needs of women who face the choice of whether to have an abortion and the particular ways in which their decisions may affect their lives and the lives of their families. This approach also would address social and legal aspects of the abortion debate, such as the fact that, though abortion affects the lives of women much more directly than it does the lives of men, women as a group are significantly underrepresented in the institutions that create abortion-related laws and regulations.
The four-principles approach
Whereas some approaches in bioethics proceed by applying principles derived from independent ethical theories to individual cases (a “top-down” approach), others proceed by examining individual cases in order to elucidate the principles that seem to guide most people’s thinking about bioethical issues in actual practice (a “bottom-up” approach). One very influential approach along these lines, known as the “four principles” of bioethics, attempts to describe a set of minimum moral conditions on the behaviour of health care professionals. The first principle, autonomy, entails that health care professionals should respect the autonomous decisions of competent adults. The second principle, beneficence, holds that they should aim to do good—i.e., to promote the interests of their patients. The third principle, nonmaleficence, requires that they should do no harm. Finally, the fourth principle, justice, holds that they should act fairly when the interests of different individuals or groups are in competition—e.g., by promoting the fair allocation of health care resources.
According to proponents of the four-principles approach, one of its advantages is that, because the principles are independent of any particular ethical theory, they can be used by theorists working in a variety of different traditions. Both the utilitarian and the Kantian, it is argued, can support the principle of autonomy, though they would do so for different reasons. Nevertheless, this adaptability may also be construed as a disadvantage. Critics have contended that the principles are so general that whatever agreement on them there may be is unlikely to be very meaningful. Thus, although the utilitarian and the Kantian may both accept the principle of autonomy, the principle as it is formulated allows them to understand the notion of autonomy in very different ways. Another criticism of the approach is that it does not offer any clear way of prioritizing between the principles in cases where they conflict—as they are often liable to do. The principle of autonomy, for example, might conflict with the principle of beneficence in cases where a competent adult patient refuses to accept life-saving treatment.
Despite these problems, the principles remain useful as a framework in which to think about moral issues in medicine and the life sciences. This is not an inconsiderable contribution, for, on at least one conception of the field, the main task of bioethics is not so much to provide answers to moral problems as to identify where the problems lie.
The significance of public attitudes
Since its inception the field of bioethics has been populated by specialists from a number of different disciplines, including primarily philosophers, lawyers, and theologians. In the last decade of the 20th century, however, the contributions of social scientists to bioethical research became particularly important. Work of this type involved surveys of public attitudes to advances in the life sciences, including xenotransplantation and genetic modification. Programs for facilitating public understanding of these advances were developed, leading to the establishment of “public understanding” and later “public engagement,” or “participation,” as distinct topics of study in bioethics and the social sciences.
These topics have been important from both a practical and a theoretical point of view. In order to formulate sound public policies on issues such as human cloning, for example, it is important to be able to predict how such technology, were it to become widely available, would affect the public’s decision making about reproduction. At the same time, research on public attitudes may reveal that some bioethical principles, such as the principle of autonomy, may not be suitable for some societies, particularly those with cultures that are not particularly individualistic. For these societies, something like a “principle of solidarity” may have greater relevance. Nevertheless, it would be a mistake to assume that one of these principles must apply to the exclusion of the other—it is possible for a society to value both autonomy and solidarity.
Policy making
The importance of the social and legal issues addressed in bioethics is reflected in the large number of national and international bodies established to advise governments on appropriate public policy. At the national level, several countries have set up bioethics councils or commissions, including the President’s Council on Bioethics in the United States, the Det Etiske Råd (Danish Council of Ethics) in Denmark, and the Comité Consultatif National d’Ethique (National Consultative Bioethics Committee) in France. Elsewhere, as in the United Kingdom, there are a variety of different bodies that consider bioethical issues. The Nuffield Council on Bioethics has taken on the role of a national bioethics committee to a certain extent, but there also are national bodies that deal with specific fields, such as the Human Genetics Commission.
Several international organizations also are involved in policy making on bioethical issues. The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO), for example, has an International Bioethics Committee; the Human Genome Organisation has an Ethics Committee; and the Council of Europe has issued the Convention on Human Rights and Biomedicine. The proliferation of such committees is evidence of the increasing political influence of the work performed by bioethicists. Indeed, acquaintance with developments in bioethics arguably is becoming an important aspect of national and global citizenship. At the same time, however, the role of bioethical experts on advisory or decision-making bodies has itself become a topic of study in bioethics.
Global bioethics
The field of bioethics has grown most rapidly in North America, Australia and New Zealand, and Europe. Cross-cultural discussion also has expanded and in 1992 led to the establishment of the International Association of Bioethics. A significant discussion under way at the start of the 21st century concerned the possibility of a “global” bioethics that would be capable of encompassing the values and cultural traditions of non-Western societies. Some bioethicists maintained that a global bioethics could be founded on the four-principles approach, in view of its apparent compatibility with widely differing ethical theories and worldviews. Others argued to the contrary that the four principles are not an appropriate basis for a global bioethics because at least some of them—in particular the principle of autonomy—reflect peculiarly Western values. Although the issue remains unresolved, the field as a whole continues to grow in sophistication. At the same time, the increasing pace of technological advances in medicine and the life sciences demands that bioethicists continually rethink the basic assumptions of their field and reflect carefully on their own methodologies.
CITATION INFORMATION
ARTICLE TITLE: Bioethics
WEBSITE NAME: Encyclopaedia Britannica
PUBLISHER: Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc.
DATE PUBLISHED: 27 May 2019
ACCESS DATE: December 17, 2019
Introduction
Biotechnology, at its core, is about understanding life and using this knowledge to benefit people. Many see biotechnology as a significant force in improving the quality of people’s lives in the 21st century. Obviously, biotechnology is intimately tied to science and scientific knowledge. I will argue that biotechnology is also closely tied to ethics. At the very least, biotechnology promotes a certain vision of life, one in which some things are viewed as good and to be encouraged or pursued, and other things are bad and should be avoided or eliminated. That vision influences people’s choices and what is viewed as ethically appropriate. A two-way flow exists in which ethics influences biotechnology even while the science impacts ethics.
At times, the relationship between biotechnology and ethics is portrayed as one of conflict. Sometimes the impression is conveyed that ethics is needed only when someone wants to tell others that what they are doing is wrong. To a degree, this is understandable since controversy, debate and argument are usually integral to ethics discussions.
But ethics is just as important when there is consensus that a direction is good and right. The role of ethics is often invisible at this stage. There wasn’t an ethical debate over whether to search for a cure for cancer. But the decision to pursue such research was motivated by a common vision that curing cancer was the ethical thing to do. Ethical examination of issues is important not only as a form of critique but also to identify and celebrate the right things people do.
The effort, resources and creativity focussed on developing better treatments are ethically laudable. As such, there is much to celebrate about biotechnology. Society and individuals have benefited in many ways from technology. Many technological developments protect people from illnesses and natural disasters, giving some people “liberation from the tyranny of nature” (Barbour 1993, p. 4). In some parts of the world, people have higher living standards. Travel and communication have developed in unprecedented ways. Many of these changes can be welcomed as ethical developments.
Yet at the same time, other ethical considerations must be considered. At what price are some of these developments realised? Some developments seem motivated by a desire to find treatment at any price. Assisted human reproduction is a particularly controversial area where biotechnological treatment of infertility leads to many ethical dilemmas. Even with less controversial conditions like heart disease or cancer, developments have left people with high expectations that cures should exist. Some are concerned that technological developments lead to dehumanisation or in healthcare lead to less emphasis on caring. Ethical concerns exist about justice, and how fairly these technological benefits are distributed—both within society and around the world. With all the options now available for some, concerns are raised about whether too much choice is bad for us (Schwartz 2004).
Overall, though, technology has a strong ethical foundation. The appropriate response to misgivings and concerns is not to reject technology. “By turning our backs on technological change, we would be expressing our satisfaction with current levels of hunger, disease, and privation... We simply cannot stop while there are masses to feed and diseases to conquer, seas to explore and heavens to survey” (Florman 1981, p. 193).
The benefits of technology, realised and potential, point to a technological mandate: biotechnology should strive to benefit people’s lives. Many of the concerns about technology can be traced to the technological imperative: the idea that something should be developed because we can, or we think we can. The distinction between a technological mandate and the technological imperative rests on the ultimate goals of biotechnology. Before addressing whether it can be done, research must answer, “Why should it be done?”
The goals of biotechnology
Ethics includes assessment of the rights and wrongs of specific technologies and applications (like cloning or genetic diagnosis). Another important pursuit within ethics is examining the broader goals and aims of enterprises like biotechnology. The relief of sickness is one goal, but there are others that can be more ethically controversial.
Aubrey de Grey (2006) at Cambridge University has suggested that biotechnology should be directed towards “engineered negligible senescence.” He stated, “I’m about indefinite extension of longevity... Average lifespan would be in the region of 1,000 years... seriously.” De Grey claims that over the next 25 years enough progress will be made in biotechnology to allow people to extend their lives long enough to obtain the next set of benefits. In this way, little by little, people will live longer and longer, effectively preventing death.
Developing the necessary biotechnology for engineered negligible senescence assumes that indefinite life extension is good for humanity. Even if accepted as an ethical goal, it would be one goal among many. Would it be the most appropriate goal for biotechnology? This question is especially pertinent given the limited resources available for biotechnology. Resources are also needed for education, to better distribute the healthcare resources already available, and to provide debt relief for poorer nations. How much investment towards the goal of indefinite life-extension would be in keeping with global justice? While people in developed countries can expect to live into their 80s, the average life expectancy at birth in 2003 was still in the 30s in some African countries (World Health Organisation 2005).
These types of questions require ethical evaluation. Time should be taken to reflect on the broader implications of pursuing biotechnology. For example, the Center for Responsible Nanotechnology claims that “much industry can be directly replaced by molecular manufacturing.” The economic fall-out from such developments would be immense, leading to significant social changes with the potential for good and harm. These ethical issues need careful examination even before the technological issues are resolved.
Taking the time to reflect on these aspects of scientific developments can be difficult, especially with the pace and focus within biotechnology. The pressures of competing for funding, making breakthroughs, securing intellectual property, and obtaining market share all push against calls for caution or time-consuming reflection. Technological development can seem like a motorway, everyone on the fast track to success. Ethics, even when well intentioned, can seem like a diversion or a road-block that prevents biotechnology reaching its destination, or delays it inexcusably.
However, there is a growing realisation that ethics must be a part of the planning process within biotechnology. In many areas of research, ethics does impact the design of scientific experiments. Any research involving human or animal participants will be scrutinised by ethics committees. The methodology must conform with ethical codes and guidelines. An argument can be made that publicly funded research should be conducted in ways that conform with society’s values. “When the nation decides an activity is worth its public money, it declares that the activity is valued, desired, and favored” (President’s Council on Bioethics 2004, p. 38). Therefore it is important to ensure that what is publicly funded is ethically acceptable in society. The goal of relieving suffering is widely accepted, yet it must be balanced against other societal goals. The ethics of proposed biotechnological developments must be scrutinised carefully.
The darker side
Even such a laudable goal as relieving human suffering cannot be taken as condoning any and all biotechnology. Humanity’s creativeness and resourcefulness have long been recognised and praised. But human activity can have a darker side. The ancient Greek philosopher Sophocles reflected on these two sides of technological development. On the one hand he noted many human accomplishments in transport, agriculture and medicine. But he also pointed to problems with this same inventiveness.
“Many the wonders but nothing more wondrous than man....Clever beyond all dreamsthe inventive craft that he haswhich may drive him one time or another to well or ill.When he honors the laws of the land and the gods’ sworn right high indeed is his city;but stateless the man who dares to do what is shameful” (cited in Jonas 1984, p. 2).
The human capacity for good or evil, whether intended or unintended, impacts how people view the ethics of technology. Hans Jonas fled Germany during the Nazi era and eventually taught philosophy in New York. One of his life’s projects was to develop an ethics for technology. His approach was based on his conviction that the new technological age raises several ethical challenges that earlier technology did not have to address. “Modern technology has introduced actions of such novel scale, objects, and consequences that the framework of former ethics can no longer contain them” (Jonas 1984, p. 6). Biotechnology is a particularly fitting example of technology with such fundamentally different characteristics that it requires a careful re-examination of how its ethical dimensions are evaluated. Biotechnology “raises moral questions that are not simply difficult in the familiar sense but are of an altogether different kind” (Habermas 2003, p. 14).
Challenging characteristics of biotechnology
The vulnerability of nature
Jonas contends that ethics prior to the new technological age focussed on human–human interactions. Human dealings with the non-human world were regarded as ethically neutral. The capacity for new technology to have global impact shows that ethics needs to broaden its focus. Environmental problems and the existence of nuclear technology demonstrate the importance of ethical examination of more than just human–human interactions.
New technology also highlights the vulnerability of nature. Previous technological developments appeared to assume that natural resources were in endless supply and that nature could rebound from any human impact. Environmental changes show these assumptions were problematic. Ethical evaluations of biotechnology need to take the vulnerability of nature into account. These issues also point to limitations in previous ethical approaches that focussed only on humans. At the same time, a concern for these broader issues can lead to new technological challenges and exciting research opportunities, such as has occurred with research into renewal energy sources stemming from ethical concern for the environment.
Limitations with rights
Rights-based approaches to ethics have made important contributions to human welfare. They provide a means by which vulnerable humans can argue for more ethical treatment. However, such approaches have their limitations (O’Mathúna et al. 2005). A rights-based approach can become very individualistic, with each party focussed on his or her rights. Access to biotechnology and new treatments can be defended on the basis of individual rights and personal autonomy. Yet this approach does not lend itself easily to concerns about people seeking treatments that are ethically questionable or of uncertain benefit. For example, individuals may want reproductive cloning, but the concerns of future generations and society as a whole need to be considered. Rights-based approaches are problematic in these situations since rights are typically held by individuals and are not given to those who do not as yet exist.
A rights-based approach to ethics must include some method of identifying those who bear rights. Those who have rights place duties on others to uphold those rights. It has proved very difficult to find consensus on how rights are to be ascribed. One approach is that all humans are inherently entitled to all human rights. This raises questions about when a human is given these rights (at fertilisation or birth or some other point). It also leaves no guidance on how to treat the non-human world. Biotechnology requires answers to these questions to address ethical concerns about non-human species and nature as a whole. This has led to an approach where rights are granted based on particular abilities and attributes. There is little consensus over what abilities entitle an organism to rights. Philosophically, it is also difficult to justify why any particular attribute should lead to the granting of rights. The whole approach is criticised as being motivated by a desire to treat unethically those not given rights. This is particularly relevant to research on human embryos, especially embryonic stem cell research.
Developments in biotechnology point to serious limitations with a rights-based approach to ethics. Rather than providing insurmountable problems for ethics, these point to the need for a different approach to ethics. Jonas and others point out that rather than focussing exclusively on human rights and entitlements, the new technological era requires a greater focus on human responsibility.
Future consequences
Earlier technology impacted humans and their lives, but did not have the potential to change human nature. Biotechnology does. With that comes the potential for broader and long-range consequences. Predictions about these consequences can be difficult and unreliable. This is particularly cogent with genetic technology. The consequences of our ability to manipulate the human genome could impact many, if not all, future generations. The way genes interact with one another means that manipulating one gene could have unintended effects on other genes or their expressed proteins. This is especially important given the recent realisation that the human genome contains fewer genes than originally presumed.
Biotechnology’s mistakes may produce problems, but so too might its successes. As technology has developed and spread, “the more all of reality is seen as matter-of-factly material and hence as controllable in a completely technical and rational manner” (Schuurman 2005, pp. 16–17). Successful technological solutions could lead people to view all our problems as needing a technological fix. The medicalisation of patients and the instrumentalisation of people are consequences of technology’s successes. This can have a dehumanising effect on human life, which makes it easier to treat some humans as less than fully human. This is a way in which technology can take on a life of its own and have much more profound ethical consequences.
Biotechnology has the added capacity to produce products that literally do take on life. The technology humans developed in the past was inanimate and could be left unused if found to be ethically problematic—as difficult as that might have been. However, biotechnology now makes possible the creation of products that are themselves alive. “The work of [human] hands takes on a life of its own and independent force, no longer figuratively but literally” (Jonas 2004, p. 570). The living products of biotechnology are no longer under human control in the way an inanimate machine was. Now the living product itself could influence its impact and might develop into new forms of life with unexpected consequences (although such problems have not developed to date with genetically modified bacteria).
Such factors should remind us of the place of awe and mystery in the face of nature. We humans are limited in our ability to understand, control and direct nature. That realisation should cause us to pause before attempting to manipulate life through biotechnology. It should lead to a sense of caution. Yet often the very opposite is the case, with the pressure to rush to be the first to develop something new. The precautionary principle is particularly pertinent with experimentation on humans.
Impact on human nature and personhood
No area of biotechnology more clearly brings to focus the need for careful ethical reflection than its potential to impact human nature. Previous technology has provided new tools that impacted human activities and society. Humans were the makers of technology. Some aspects of biotechnology now make humans the objects of technology. Humans have turned upon themselves and are ready “to make over the maker of all the rest” (Jonas 1984, p. 18). The capacity for biotechnology to create and change human lives calls for careful reflection on what it means to be human and the place of human personhood. According to the contemporary German philosopher, Jürgen Habermas (2003, p. 13),
“For as soon as adults treat the desirable genetic traits of their descendents as a product they can shape according to a design of their own liking, they are exercising a kind of control over their genetically manipulated offspring that ... should only be exercised over things, not persons.”
This, he continues, “results from obliterating the boundary between persons and things.” Recent developments with stem cell research and cloning have been the lightning rod for debate over human personhood. These discussions point to the gulf between proponents on the different sides. Some have viewed embryos as “featureless bundles of cells” (Pearson 2002, p. 15). From this perspective the human embryo is a human non-person that can be used and destroyed in research. Others disagree and maintain that the human embryo should be treated as a person, making it unethical to treat it merely as a means to others’ ends.
Personhood can be viewed as an inherent attribute of all humans. This confers all humans with certain rights and determines how persons should be treated ethically. This approach protects humans, especially the vulnerable, from unethical treatment. The other approach makes personhood conditional on reaching some stage of development or possessing certain abilities. Only humans with those capacities are then entitled to protection. A fundamental problem with this approach is that it always arises to justify killing those declared to be human non-persons. How will it affect us to treat human lives as commodities to be manipulated and destroyed at will? When we justify doing so with embryos, will it become easier to do so at later stages of development?
This debate points to the difficulty of determining public policy when sections of society have irreconcilable positions on matters of fundamental importance. We must also examine how biotechnology itself impacts our view of human nature. Leon Kass asks how will it affect us “to look upon nascent human life as a natural resource to be mined, exploited, commodified. The little embryos are merely destroyed, but we—their users—are at risk of corruption” (Kass 2002, p. 10). This is much more than a debate over rights. This is about human dignity, including what it means for humans to act with dignity. This changes the focus from ascribing rights to determining responsibilities.
Central place of responsibility
The enormity of the potential impact of biotechnology on human nature should cause us to proceed cautiously. Biotechnology has the potential to do great good. But it also has the potential to cause much harm. This could arise in the physical realm through unexpected consequences of the technology itself. But other harms could arise through the non-physical impacts of biotechnology. Cars and computers have affected many aspects of human life and society. Biotechnology could change what it means to be human.
A rights approach to ethics makes clear where people have rights. Each right carries a corollary duty or responsibility. If people have a right to healthcare, someone has the responsibility to provide healthcare resources. Much energy has been expended identifying and defending human rights. We now need a similar emphasis on human responsibilities.
Responsibility is also a corollary of power. Biotechnology brings new powers to humanity. These powers should remind us of our responsibility to nature and the environment, to all of life, to the future, and to human nature and personhood. To understand these responsibilities entails the development of wisdom. That wisdom requires ethical reflection before developing specific forms of biotechnology. Taking the time for that reflection can go against the pace of biotechnological developments and hubris over human wisdom.
Jonas warned that new technology was propelling us towards a utopian future. Aubrey de Grey exemplifies that vision for biotechnology. These developments have the potential for much good, but also risk changing, harming or even destroying some species, including ourselves. To make the right ethical decisions “requires supreme wisdom—an impossible situation for man in general, because he does not possess that wisdom, and in particular for contemporary man, because he denies the very existence of its object, objective value and truth. We need wisdom most when we believe in it least” (Jonas 1984, p. 21).
Jonas was referring to the post-modern rejection of objective truth that has become so prevalent—the idea that all answers are equally valid. In contrast, ethics searches for better answers to ethical questions. It acknowledges the limitations in current wisdom, and strives to improve our understanding. The way forward is muddied by our inability to accurately predict the consequences of proposed biotechnological developments. Some argue that we should push ahead and deal with problems as they arise. But given the scale of disaster that biotechnological mistakes could trigger, Jonas’ guiding principle contains much wisdom. He argued that “ignorance of the ultimate implications becomes itself a reason for responsible restraint—as the second best to the possession of wisdom itself” (Jonas 1984, p. 22).
Time and resources must be committed to examining the ethical implications of proposed biotechnological developments. The potential impact on all aspects of nature must be considered. The social, emotional and spiritual implications of developments in biotechnology must also be examined. When humans themselves are the objects of biotechnology, great caution is necessary lest we promote a view of ourselves and our neighbours as nothing more than living bits of technology.